Paging Dr. Bronson
February 28th, 2013

Speaking of death wishes, the APA may be considering taking out a contract on Joel Dimsdale. He was the head of the Somatic Symptoms Disorders work group, the DSM-5 committee in charge of revising criteria for, you guessed it, psychosomatic disorders. That category is a quagmire, largely because of the confusions we’ve inherited from four hundred years of mind/body dualism, but that’s a story for a different day. The story for today is what Dimsdale said to ABC News.

Background: The DSM-5 is introducing Somatic Symptoms Disorder a diagnosis for which patients will qualify if they have “one or more somatic symptoms that are distressing and/or result in significant disruption in daily life,”‘ and if they have “persistent thoughts about the seriousness” of the symptoms, “persistent anxiety” about them, or devote “excessive time and energy” to them. Up late at night googling that pain in your gut? Be careful, you might be mentally ill.

I’d fully deconstruct this, but I’m supposed to be proofreading my book, and besides I trust you can see just how stupid this diagnosis is. In case you can’t then check out Allen Frances’s blog about it.  The point here is what happened when ABC asked Dimsdale to comment on the objections being raised by people whose “somatic symptoms” are severe or complex enough to make persistent thoughts and anxiety inescapable and who must devote lots of time and energy (sat in a waiting room lately?) to them. Adding psychiatric diagnosis is just insult to injury, they said, and will only help doctors–who famously can’t stand patients who refuse to have something they can cure–dismiss them as nutcases.

“Some people feel like a diagnosis is a Scarlet Letter, but actually those in the DSM-4 were quite stigmatizing and pejorative,” Dimsdale said, by way of justifying the change. You would think that a guy smart enough to be a doctor would not invoke a novel whose villain has the same last name as he does, who is in fact one of the most notorious bad guys  (and hypocrites) in American literature, but that is not the dumbest thing he said. The dumbest thing he said was, “If it doesn’t work, we’ll fix it in the DSM-5.1 or DSM-6.”

Not that this is not exactly the way that the DSM-5 leaders think. Indeed, it’s a version of something they’ve said repeatedly: that the DSM is a living document, not a Bible. (Forgetting, of course, that many religious people, although perhaps not Hawthorne’s Dimmesdale, think the Bible is a living document.) But to say this in the context of explaining a diagnosis that could be applied to just about anyone with  a serious or debilitating disease, to acknowledge that they (and the rest of us) will be the involuntary subjects of a massive public health experiment, to bring attention to the APA’s apparent obliviousness to the real world effects of the DSM, to what happens to people when they are diagnosed and undiagnosed–really, I’ve been around this story for two years now, and even I find this shocking.

I’d say the APA would have to clean up this mess. But they’ve gone into hiding. Or more accurately, they’re just running out the clock, which they can do because they own the ball. But I wonder if behind the scenes they’re taking Dr Dimsdale out to the woodshed. Or the stocks.

 

Update: A reliable source assures me that Dimsdale knows full well who his namesake is and was just making an inside joke. Which is pretty funny, I’ll admit, although I doubt he intended all the layers of irony. But (and this is admittedly the pot calling the kettle black) it’s sort of cavalier, given the stakes. You gotta know your audience.




Does the American Psychiatric Association Have a Death Wish?
February 26th, 2013

The American Psychiatric Association has placed an advertorial in JAMA touting the virtues of the DSM-5. It’s a classic of the form–as they say in Texas, all hat and no cattle, or, as I say in my forthcoming Book of Woe, all clothes and no emperor.

“Many of the revisions in DSM-5 will help psychiatry better resemble the rest of medicine,” they write. This has been the dream of psychiatry since about 1847, when the APA was first founded (although then it was known as the Association of Superintendents of American Institutions for the Insane): to be taken seriously by the rest of medicine. And at least since 1917, when the APA (by then known as the American Medico-Psychological Association) heard from the head of its committee on nomenclature that diagnostic chaos was undermining the specialty’s credibility, it has seen the diagnostic manual as crucial to its standing in the medical profession, and in the world at large.

So have they succeeded? Is the title of the JAMA piece–“DSM-5: The Future Arrived”–accurate? For that matter, does it even make sense? Is arrived a past tense verb, meaning that the DSM-5 is some kind of visitation, as if the future showed up one day on the APA’s doorstep and left behind this message? Or is it a gerundive, a verb form used as an adjective? In which case, you have to wonder exactly what an arrived future looks like, and how it differs from one that is still traveling.

Anyway, I digress. Plus which I am sick of helping the APA explain itself. So I’ll let their words do the talking.

Many of the revisions in DSM-5 will help psychiatry better resemble the rest of medicine, including the use of dimensional (eg, quantitative) approaches. Disorder boundaries are often unclear to even the most seasoned clinicians and underscore the proliferation of residual diagnoses (ie, “not otherwise specified” disorders) from DSM-IV. But a large proportion of DSM-5 users will not be psychiatrists; most patients, for instance, will first present to their primary care physician—not to a psychiatrist—when experiencing psychiatric symptoms. The use of definable thresholds that exist on a continuum of normality is already present throughout much of general medicine, such as in blood pressure and cholesterol measurement, and these thresholds aid physicians in more accurately detecting pathology and determining appropriate intervention. Thus DSM-5 provides a model that should be recognizable to nonpsychiatrists and should facilitate better diagnosis and follow-up care by such clinicians.

I dare you to parse this passage without exploding your own head. No, here, let me do it for you. I’ve been taking Vaccutrix, the new drug that keeps your head from exploding when parsing nonsense, and which I would recommend for anyone unfortunate enough to have to follow the logic of psychiatric diagnosis. The first sentence promises that the DSM-5 will make psychiatry fit into modern medicine by providing dimensional measures, i.e., ways to measure disorders that resemble the methods doctors use to diagnosing other conditions. The second sentence  reminds readers that diagnostic boundaries are porous and poorly defined, which means that accurate diagnosis is hard–so hard that even the specialists can’t do it, let alone the primary care docs whom most people see first. The third sentence suggests that the best way to make this whole thing easier is to have measures like blood pressure and cholesterol that help set the diagnostic thresholds and that bring psychiatry in line with common sense, which tells us that most people’s psychological problems are extreme versions of normal behaviors or experiences.

Now here is where you would expect the APA to tell you what they have done to make diagnosing mental disorders more like measuring blood pressure and less like throwing darts, and thus to bring about the Arrived Future. But that part seems to be missing. This doesn’t stop them from leading their last sentence with “thus,” as if they had actually proved something in the paragraph. Which they did not. They merely reasserted what they wrote at the outset: that the DSM-5 is going to bring psychiatry in line with medicine. They have restated  their premise as their conclusion, using the old schoolboy trick of inserting a “thus”  in front of the topic sentence and declaring QED. It’s the equivalent of the army declaring victory in Vietnam as they beat a retreat, only in this case there aren’t videos of people clinging to the runners of helicopters taking off from the embassy roof. (At least not yet. Wait until the DSM comes out. And my book.)

I said I was tired of explaining the APA, but I can’t resist. They made this fundamental logical error for a reason–indeed for the same one that the schoolboy makes it. Which is that they don’t have any evidence, and it’s not because the dog ate their homework. It’s because there are no dimensional measures in the DSM-5. They tried to develop and implement them, but the effort was hurried and chaotic and poorly planned and ultimately soundly rejected by the membership of the APA. The dimensional approach was going to be the signal achievement of the DSM-5 (that is, after the first signal achievement, the tying of neuroscientific findings to DSM disorders, had to be abandoned for lack of evidence); it didn’t pan out. The APA leadership is understandably reluctant to own up to this fact. What is astonishing, and nearly inexplicable, unless you’ve been watching this whole train wreck unfold, is that it would insist–in JAMA, no less, the flagship product of teh AMerican Medical Association–that they had succeeded where they had failed, and to think that that little magic word–thus–would somehow win the day for them.

Does the APA have some kind of death wish?

PS=–Lest you think this is my antipsychiatrist animus speaking, this is from a source inside the DSM-5 revision effort:

This statement has no relationship to the actual DSM-5.   There are dimensional measures in the non-official Section III, however.   But that still has nothing to do with “definable thresholds that exist on a continuum.”   I would have hoped that had the reviewers of this editorial actually known anything about what DSM-5 was going to look like they would have prevented such statements from being included.

 No relationship to the DSM. In other words, no relationship to reality. In other words psychotic.




Sneak Peek
February 22nd, 2013

 

This is the cover for my new book. I think it’s self-explanatory.

 If I were really savvy, I’d have posted this and the alternatives a long time ago and submitted to the wisdom of the crowd. But I’m not. Greenberg_jacket




From the Mailbag
February 22nd, 2013

In response to my comment that maybe the DSM-5 doesn’t matter, Rebecca writes

Having a bipolar diagnosis will get you rejected from underwritten health insurance for the self-employed – even if you apply for a policy that specifically excludes mental health coverage (as I did). And you can’t get the faux bipolar diagnosis removed from your medical record because even if it’s a fad diagnosis there is no way to prove that you don’t have it once you’ve been labelled.

This is a great example of why the DSM does matter, even if the particulars of DSM-5 don’t (at least not so much). It’s also a totally underappreciated aspect of using medical insurance to pay for mental health treatment. The diagnosis your therapist puts on your bill, those innocuous-seeming 4 or 5 digits that he or she may or may not even mention to you or may assure you are merely a formality, will become part of your permanent medical dossier. And as electronic medical records become the law of the land, the diagnosis will not be something that someone has to dig around in the paperwork to find.

Rebecca writes of one of the implications: you might be denied health insurance in the future. In the Obamacare era, you won’t be denied, but you may well be put into the assigned risk pool, or whatever it is eventually called, and your premiums increased accordingly. But  you may be denied life insurance and, who knows, as all our datalives converge in the Mother Computer, your credit rating, your car insurance premiums, your employment prospects, and so on may also be affected.

And that’s not all. I have a patient who has chronic illnesses that sometimes become acute and life threatening. Her array of symptoms and syndromes is so vast and complicated and confusing, and so confounded by the interactions among her treatments, that she stumps every doctor that comes into contact with her. Once, when hospitalized at a leading university medical center, a psychiatric evaluation was ordered, and she was diagnosed with Somatoform Disorder, largely on the basis of a Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Inventory, an old-line personality test that has among its features a hypochondriasis scale. Conventional wisdom holds that the Hs scale is not valid for people who are actually sick (duh!), but that didn’t stop the clinician, a psychiatrist who spent 45 minutes with the patient and then read the test results, from rendering the diagnosis. Since that time, when she has been hospitalized, and especially when she has been hospitalized in a new (to her) hospital, doctors confronted with her bewildering array of symptoms have seized this one diagnosis to decide that she is a mental patient. She, naturally, objects, and I have often had to enter the fray to try to straighten out the situation–a job at which I am only partly successful.

Moral of the story (and of Rebecca’s comment): Be careful about getting yourself diagnosed. It can haunt you all your life. It might be worth shelling out your own hard-earned cash for therapy to keep yourself safe.




Does the DSM-5 Even Matter?
February 12th, 2013

Maybe not. And I’m not just saying that because, having spent way too much of my life in the last couple years thinking and writing about it, the subject has become tiresome. It’s also because the two most important reasons to take the DSM, any DSM, seriously enough to worry about it at all are that it increases treatment, with all the financial and psychochemical burdens that imposes, and that it changes the way people think of their suffering, and therefore of themselves, or, to put it another way, that the DSM plays a role in the formation of identity.

But there is reason to think that both of these are overblown concerns. When it comes to the drug question, the worry is that increased diagnosis will increase the prescription of drugs. And there is no doubt that this has proven to be the case in many instances. For instance, shortly after the introduction of Bipolar Disorder II in the DSM-IV, Abilify, Zyprexa, and the other atypical antipsychotic drugs shot to the top of the sales charts. But does it follow that the diagnosis caused the increase? While it may seem obvious that it did, it’s important to remember that doctors can prescribe any drug for any condition they see fit. That is exactly what happened with the childhood bipolar scandal: an astronomical and catastrophic increase in prescriptions of antipsychotics, with no change to the DSM.  Because while a drug company needs a DSM diagnosis to get an indication from the FDA–the right to market the drug for a particular use–there’s nothing to stop a drug company from paying for a study showing that their products can be used to treat a condition not in the DSM and from publicizing that finding. So it’s conceivable that Pharma could have created the right buzz around the atypicals to encourage docs to prescribe them for patients who don’t respond to antidepressants, even without the new diagnostic category. Indeed, much of the increase in use of atypicals is not due to increased bipolar II diagnoses, but rather to the buzz the industry has created about using the atypicals to “boost” the antidepressants in “treatment-resistant depression”-a category you won’t find in the DSM.

Another example: the big worry over the removal of the bereavement exclusion (BE) from the depression diagnosis in the DSM-5 is that it will lead to more prescriptions of antidepressants. In some cases, as in this Atlantic blog, this isn’t a worry, but a virtue of the change: by identifying people whose grief is an expression of an underlying disorder, the removal of the exclusion makes it more likely they will get the appropriate treatment. But as inveterate data miners Ramin Mojtabai and Mark Olfson have pointed out, 72 percent of antidepressant prescriptions are written in the absence of a diagnosis of a mental disorder. Doctors, in other words, are already prescribing drugs regardless of diagnosis. Which to me means that the docs who are already prescribing Prozac to grieving widows and widowers will continue to do so, and those who think they should hold off will also continue to do so. It is possible that some psychiatrists were feeling restrained by the BE, but pharmacological restraint isn’t exactly psychiatrists’ long suit, and even if it was , and now they start handing out the prescriptions more generously, psychiatrists are only writing 20 percent of the prescriptions for antidepressants in the first place. My prediction: removing the BE will lead to a negligible increase in prescriptions, because docs started giving out the drugs to the bereaved a long time ago. And people started wanting to use drugs to change how their lives felt even longer ago.

So what about the identity issue? If I tell a moody woman she has Bipolar Disorder II, or a widower that he has Bereavement-Related Depression, does this make a big difference? Of course, steeped as I am in a Foucaultian tea (or is it Kool-Aid?), and having written an entire tome on the subject, I’m  sort of obligated to think so. And indeed I do. But you can’t just present the public with a random list of labels to affix to their troubles and thus to themselves. The list has to be plausible, of course, and it has to have authority–accomplished in the DSM by calling it a medical text–but it also has to resonate with the marketplace. It has to strike a chord. And in a market of people shopping for identities, illness is a hot commodity, especially when it comes to explaining what we don’t like about ourselves, what is troublesome or inconvenient, what makes us anxious about our prospects or those of our children.

Forty years ago, Peter Sedgwick wrote that “the future belongs to illness.” Forty years later, the future has arrived, and the DSM is only one way in which his prophecy has been fulfilled. There are so many benefits to illness–money, sympathy, recognition, an end to wondering about identity–that it is no wonder that a book like the DSM attracts so much notice, and that changes to it are highly contentious. But I believe that we could still be using the DSM-I, with its psychoneurotic disorders like depressive reaction and its transient situational personality disorders like adjustment reaction of later life to label ourselves and each other, to rationalize our drug use, to submit our confusions to experts. IN this respect, the DSM-5 doesn’t really matter, at least not in its specifics. It only matters as a vernacular, as the current language that experts use to tell us who we are.